Processing math: 0%

2018년 7월 31일 화요일

0.3 Axiom of Choice and Equivalents (Zorn's lemma, Hausdorff's maximal principle, Well ordering and Tukey's Lemma)

Now we discuss fundamental axiom of set theory - Axiom of Choice.
The following are equivalent.
  1. (The Hausdorff Maximal Principle). Every partially ordered set has a maximal linearly ordered subset.
  2. (Zorn's Lemma). If X is partially ordered set and every linearly ordered subset of X has an upper bound, then X has a maximal element.
  3. (Well Ordering Principle). Every nonempty set X can be well ordered.
  4. (Axiom of Choice). If \left\{ X_{a} \right\}_{a \in A} is nonempty collection of nonempty sets, then \prod_{a \in A} X_{a} is nonempty.
  5. (Tukey's Lemma). Every nonempty collection of finite character partially ordered by set inclusion has a maximal element.
We will prove the equivalence by showing (1) \implies (2) \implies (3) \implies (4) \implies (2) \implies (5) \implies (1) (\textbf{1} \implies \textbf{2}) Let (X, \leq) be partially ordered set with the following property. \text{"every linearly ordered subset of }X\text{ has an upper bound"} Then by 1, there exist maximal linearly ordered subset; namely S. Let m be an upper bound of S. If there exists an element x \in X such that m < x, then S \cup \left\{ x \right\} is also linearly ordered subset of X, contradicting to the maximality of S. So m is the maximal element of X.

(\textbf{2} \implies \textbf{3}) Let \mathcal{W} be the collection of well orderings of subsets of X. We define a partial ordering \lesssim on \mathcal{W} as follows. If \leq_{1} and \leq_{2} are well orderings on the subsets E_{1}, E_{2} of X, then (\leq_{1})\ \lesssim\ (\leq_{2}) \iff \begin{cases} E_{1} \subset E_{2},\ \leq_{1}\text{ and }\leq_{2}\text{ agrees on }E_{1} \\ \text{for all } x \in E_{2} \setminus E_{1}, y \leq x\text{ for all } y \in E_{1} \end{cases} Let S = \left\{ \leq_{\alpha} \right\}_{\alpha \in \Lambda} be linearly ordered subset of \mathcal{W}, with well ordering \leq_{\alpha} defined on E_{\alpha} \subset X.
\leq^{\ast} = \cup_{\alpha} \leq_{\alpha} is a well ordering on \cup_{\alpha} E_{\alpha}.
Pick x, y \in \cup_{\alpha} E_{\alpha}. Define I = \left\{ E_{\alpha}: \alpha \in \Lambda,\ \left\{ x, y\right\}\subset E_{\alpha} \right\} and E = \cap I.
  • If E is nonempty, pick E_{\alpha}, E_{\beta} \in I. By linear ordering of S, either (\leq_{\alpha})\ \lesssim\ (\leq_{\beta}) or vice versa. Either case, x \leq_{\alpha} y \iff x \leq_{\beta} y or y \leq_{\alpha} x \iff y \leq_{\beta} x so \leq^{\ast} is well defined.
  • If E is empty, x \in E_{\alpha}, y \in E_{\beta} for \alpha \neq \beta. But then by linear ordering of S, either (\leq_{\alpha})\ \lesssim\ (\leq_{\beta}) or vice versa, which induces inclusion relation between E_{\alpha} and E_{\beta}. This implies either one of them includes both elements x and y; contradiction.
Now suppose M is nonempty subset of \cup_{\alpha} E_{\alpha} such that has no least element. Then there exist a sequence \left\{ x_{n} \right\} \subset X such that x_{1} {}^{\ast}> x_{2} {}^{\ast}> ... {}^{\ast}> x_{n} {}^{\ast}> x_{n+1}... Now suppose x_{1} \in E_{\alpha_{1}}. Then we can deduce that all elements are in E_{\alpha_{1}}, which then {}^{\ast}> reduces to >_{\alpha_{1}}. Since >_{\alpha_{1}}, it has least element, which is contradiction. So \leq^{\ast} is a well ordering on \cup_{\alpha} E_{\alpha}.
Now back to the original proof, pick any E_{\beta} and \leq_{\beta} where \beta \in \Lambda. Clearly by definition E_{\beta} \subset \cup_{\alpha}E_{\alpha} and \leq^{\ast} agrees with \leq_{\beta} on E_{\beta}. Next for x \in \cup_{\alpha}E_{\alpha} \setminus E_{\beta}, there exist \gamma such that x \in E_{\gamma} \setminus E_{\beta}. By linear ordering of S, the only possibility is E_{\beta} \subset E_{\gamma}, so that y \leq_{\gamma} x ; which in turn y \leq^{\ast} x for all y \in E_{\beta}. This asserts that S is bounded above by \leq^{\ast}. By Zorn's Lemma, \mathcal{W} has maximal element \leq. If \leq is well ordering on some proper subset T of X, we can add single element x_{0} \in X \setminus T and define \leq' on T \cup \left\{ x_{0} \right\} by \leq' agrees with \leq on T and t \leq' x_{0} for all t \in T. This shows the only possibility of \leq is well ordering on X (whole set).

(\textbf{3} \implies \textbf{4}) Let X = \cup_{\alpha \in A} X_{\alpha}, and pick a well ordering on X. For each \alpha, define f(\alpha) to be a minimal element of X_{\alpha}. Then f \in \prod_{\alpha \in A} X_{\alpha}.

(\textbf{4} \implies \textbf{2}) Let (X, \leq) be a nonempty partially ordered set with property that every linearly ordered subset has an upper bound. For each x \in X, define S_{x} = \begin{cases} \left\{ y \in X: y > x \right\} & (\text{if } x \text{ is not maximal element of } X) \\ \left\{ x \right\} & (\text{if } x \text{ is maximal element of }X) \end{cases} Then by axiom of choice, \prod_{x \in X} S_{x} is not empty. So we've constructed a function f \in \prod_{x \in X} S_{x} such that f: X \rightarrow X,\ x \leq f(x)\ (\forall x \in X) Now by Bourbaki's Fixed Point Theorem, there exist x^{\ast} \in X such that f(x^{\ast}) = x^{\ast}. By definition of S_{x^{\ast}}, automatically x^{\ast} is the maximal element of X and Zorn's Lemma follows.

(\textbf{2} \implies \textbf{5}) Let \mathcal{F} be collection of sets that is of finite character. \subseteq is a natural partial ordering on \mathcal{F}. Let \mathcal{C} be nonempty linearly ordered subset of \mathcal{F}.
\bigcup \mathcal{C} \in \mathcal{F} .
Let M = \left\{ m_{1}, ..., m_{n} \right\} be a finite subset of \cup \mathcal{C}. Then there exist C_{i} \in \mathcal{C} for each i = 1, 2, ..., n such that m_{i} \in C_{i}. Since \mathcal{C} is linearly ordered, there is a set C_{j} among C_{i}s' such that C_{j} \supset C_{i} for all i, so that M \subset C_{j} Thus M \in \mathcal{F} as C_{j} \in \mathcal{F} and \mathcal{F} is finite character. It follows that \cup \mathcal{C} \in \mathcal{F}.
Back to original proof, it is clear that \cup \mathcal{C} is an upper bound for \mathcal{C}. By Zorn's Lemma, there is a maximal element of \mathcal{F}; which is exactly what Tukey's Lemma states.

(\textbf{5} \implies \textbf{1}) Let (X, \leq) be a partially ordered set. Define \mathcal{L} to be collection of all linearly ordered subsets of X.
(\implies) Pick L \in \mathcal{L}. Any finite subset of L is also linearly ordered (trivial). So any finite subset of L is in \mathcal{L}.
(\impliedby) Suppose all finite subsets of A \subset X are members of \mathcal{L}. Then for any finite subsets of A of the form \left\{ x,y \right\} satisfy either x \leq y or y \leq x. The union over all such two elements subsets, form A; which then makes A linearly ordered. So A \in \mathcal{L}.
This shows \mathcal{L} is of finite character, and by Tukey's Lemma there exist maximal element (which is maximal linearly ordered subset of X). Hausdorff's Maximal Principle directly follows.

댓글 없음:

댓글 쓰기

0.7 The Extended Real Number System

We briefly talk about materials in elementary real analysis. We will not prove those properties (see elementary real analysis textbook such ...